Separation of Powers and the Charismatic Presidency

16 August 2008

I wrote this entry when our Separation of Powers episode originally aired. I'm moving it up to the top since that episode is about to air again. I welcome further discusssion. KT

Later this morning, our episode "Power out of Balance? Exploring the Separation of Powers" will air. This epsiode was recorded back in July [of 2006] on Capitol Hill in a tiny little room in the basement of the building. Though the audience was small, they were quite engaged and engaging. We were there at the invitation of Congresswoman Anna Eshoo. We are most grateful to Congresswoman Eshoo for being our sponsor and for participating in the program. Our main guest during the program was Kathleen Sullivan. Kathleen was a terrific guest. They say that if the Democrats get to make a Supreme Court appointment anytime soon, Kathleen is high on the list of potential nominees. I can see why. She is very smart, very articulate, and has really deep knowledge of constitutional law. It was a pleasure having her as our guest. I've invited her to guest blog on the topic of separation of powers. But since she is a very busy woman, who knows if she'll take up the invitation. Anyway, I hope you enjoy listening to the program.

In the remainder of this post, I'll ruminate, just a little bit, on what's become of the separation of powers in our time.

The founding fathers in their considerable wisdom took the separation of powers to be a "bulwark of liberty." Indeed, they took the concentration of power into a single agency to be the very definition of tyranny. Conversely, they apparently believed that not just the formal separation of powers among the branches of the federal government and between the federal and state governments, but also what might be called the subsantive seperation of political interests to which the formally separated branches are asnwerable, was the key to a government that was unlikely to ever devolve into tyranny. By formally dividing the powers of government among competing branches and among the several states and the federal government and by making the various branches and and levels of government answerable to society in different ways that reflect different and competing constellations of "parts, interests, and classes of citizens," Madison seemd to believe, the government would incapable of trampling the rights of the citizens. Moreover, no ad hoc constellation of citizens would be able to sieze the powers of government and deploy them against the fundamental civil liberties of the remainder of the citizenry.

It's a nice sounding story, but I think the founders vastly overestimated the degree to which the formal separation of powers, even when conjoined with a substantive separation of interests, might suffice, on its own, to guard against tyranny and to protect civil liberties. This isn't a startling new inisght, of course. Jefferson saw the limits of merely procedural safe-guards to liberty right away and rightly insisted that an enumerated Bill of Rights be added to the constitution.

The founders lacked prescience on two particular fronts that have come to define the American political scene and that jointly conspire to make the formal separation of powers far less of a bulwark against tyranny than they imagined. First, the founding fathers failed to anticipate what I'll call the charismatic nature of the Presidency. Second, they failed to anticipate the extent to which partisan loyalty would come to trump institutional loyalty within the legislature. Let's consider the second thing first. The founders seemed to believe that Congress would be extremely jealous of its perogatives and would strongly resist the encroachment of the executive upon its domain. To some extent that has been true over the course of our history but mostly, it seems, at least to my non-expert eye, that Congress mostly resists encroachment when different parties control the executive and the legislative branches. When a single party controls both the executive and the legislative, partisan loyalty seems almost always to trump institutional loyalty. The current Republican House and Senate have been almost suppine in their obedience to the will of the President.

Why should that be? The answer has, I think, to do with the charismatic nature of the presidency in a time of modern communications. I'm not talking about the personal charisma of the any particular president. Many occupants of that office, including the current occupant, seem to me to be seriously charisma challenged. Indeed, it's something of a mystery how such a charismatic office has managed to have so many charisma challenged occupants.

By calling the presidency -- the office, not the occupant -- charismatic, I'm thinking about the power of the president to set the national agenda, to command national attention. The president's formal powers aren't really all that great in comparison with Congress. But the charismatic reach of the presidency far outstrips the charismatic reach of Congess. It's not just that the president speaks with a single (if sometimes incoherent and conflicted voice), while the legislature is a cacophony of competing voices. It's also the focus of the national media on every word and gesture of the president compared to its fairly shallow and desultory focus on the Congress. And it's also the fact that we spend millions and millions on seemingly endless presidential campaigns that seem largely designed to manufacture of exploit competing personality cults rather than competing subsantive agendas for action.

If you're an obscure member of congress trying to rise to greater national prominence, it's pretty hard to compete with the charisma of the presidency merely in the name of safeguarding the perogatives of the legislature. After all, if you are a member of the president's party you probably want most of what the president wants. So why insists on the perogatives of the legislature?

On the other hand, if your a member of the opposition party -- whether in the minority or the majority -- you do have some rationale, often considerable rationale --- for resisting. But not really because you are jealous as such of the perogatives of your branch. It's rather because you have allegiance to the competing party. Still when we have divided government, we get at least the shadow of what the Founders were after, because then we have not just the formal separation of powers but also the substantive diversion of interests that is nicely aligned with the formal separation of powers.

Of course, I haven't touched on the subject of the Supreme Court. But Kathleen Sullivan has a great deal to say about the court and its role in maintaining a balance between the executive and the legislative branches. I won't try to summarize what she has to say here. Instead, I'll urge you to check out the show -- which is about to begin right now.

I'm going to tune in via KALW's website. You could do the same.

 

Comments (13)


Guest's picture

Guest

Thursday, November 9, 2006 -- 4:00 PM

I don't think the Founders failed on either front.

I don't think the Founders failed on either front.
1. Washington -- the first President, rejected becoming King and self-limited his term of service. He was a Founder, and he set the example! The Ninth and Tenth Amendments, too, limit federal power (and thus the President) by leaving unenumerated rights to the people to decide in their state legislatures. And Article III prevents the President from firing the judges at-will and Congress from reducing their salaries if they dislike a decision (e.g., one limiting their powers). And the President must stand for national election -- far harder to do than to be elected to the Senate by a state legislature (under the un-amended Constitution), i.e., mere charisma won't do. So it simply isn't true that the Founders failed to understand an executive could be so charismatic that the people would be tempted to magnify his power. They specifically put in provisions that prevented the exercise of imperial power by a President!
2. Political parties mesh perfectly with the Founders' conception of faction. You seem to think that a party thinks with one hive mind and partisans all share one agenda. Not so. Each party is a coalition of various, vying factions, which is why each administration is different. Even successive administrations of the same party differ. Foreign parliamentary systems simply make express that coalition-building, in that each faction runs as its own party. But the various parties come together into a majority or minority coalition, much as our non-parliamentary system here has a majority or minority party. The difference here is that we have a winner-takes-all system, which respects small states and big states equally and keeps out fringe parties. The Naderites and the Greens and the Libertarians and the Marxists have no shot of getting into Congress (though they may spoil elections). The best shot they have is getting their most popular ideas stolen by one of the major parties. Which is good. It leads to the best ideas being a part of representative democracy, not the fringe ones. It mirrors our belief in self-governance and the market place of ideas. So what you see as partisanship is really just what the Founders described in Federalist Papers Nos. 10 and 51 and what they meant to include in the First Amendment by protecting our rights of association and to lobby.
Yet you find the political results of our system substantively flawed. Given the relative freedom American citizens have to run for office and your bully pulpit of a radio show and a tenured position at an elite academic institution, perhaps you should run for office. It might be the apathy of educated beneficiaries of American wealth -- and not the governmental structure constituted by our founding document -- that are the problem.

Guest's picture

Guest

Thursday, November 9, 2006 -- 4:00 PM

IS the problem, rather. Should have used previe

IS the problem, rather.
Should have used preview.

Guest's picture

Guest

Monday, November 13, 2006 -- 4:00 PM

It seems that a lot of fuss is being raised over t

It seems that a lot of fuss is being raised over the absoluteness of seperation of powers, and the cases of its circumvention throughout our history and in modern times. While we do not argue that seperation of powers is in any way unnecessary, we do argue that even the founders did not believe in complete and total adherence to complete seperation of powers. A good example of this argument can be found directly in the constitution, in which the framers put in an obvious sort of tension as to the absolute power of the supreme court. Art.3 Sec.1 reads, "The judicial power of the United States, shall be vested in one Supreme Court...", indicating that the judicial power belongs to the courts, that it is the courts who will decide all cases of law arising under the US constitution. However, Art. 3 Sec. 2 reads, "...the Supreme Court shall have appellate jurisdiction, both as to law and fact, with such exceptions, and under such regulations as the Congress shall make." Hence, congress can create exceptions to cases heard by the supreme court in which the supreme court has appellate jurisdiction! In the same article, the judicial power of the US was vested exclusively to the courts! So it seems that there are some hidden cases of tension in which the founders gave us ways to bypass the complete seperation of powers. Hence, we believe that while it is not a good time to run around proclaiming the end of seperation of powers, it is a time to stop running around worrying about every time the seperation is breached. So far, nothing drastic has befallen the US due to some of these trends away from the ideal, and it is arguable that the founders themselves provisioned us for turns away from complete seperation.
This comment written by students of Mr. Koepping's AP Government class, circa 2006, period 8.

Guest's picture

Guest

Monday, November 13, 2006 -- 4:00 PM

The discussion starts with a debate of the separat

The discussion starts with a debate of the separation of powers and what that entails. The inherently more interesting question, however, becomes what is the role of the president, specifically dealing with his role of ?commander in chief?, and when does this power apply.
Even though the executive branch was the most thoroughly discussed issue during the constitutional convention, and one of the most vaguely explained articles, the powers of the president are not so cleanly enumerated as those of the judicial and legislative branches.
What did the framers intend to be the power of the president by labeling him the ?commander in chief? of the armed forces? I feel that in this situation, the president has overstepped his rights as the commander of the armed forces on several occasions, which would be redundant to explain as they were clearly, and I feel accurately described in the point made by Ms. Kathleen Sullivan. As she put it, the executive right as ?commander in chief? of the armed forces does not leave him in control of the nation, or in power to command the will of the people. It is evident in the constitution of the United States of America that the framers would not have upheld his decisions in recent affairs. The framers feared monarchy more than anything else and went to very drastic measures to ensure that our country was free from it.
In areas such as the wire tapping, where it is clearly an invasion of citizens rights, congress should have stepped in and put an immediate end to it. Due to ?unhealthy partisanship?, however, the legislature allowed these unlawful to operations to continue. The members of congress feel more strongly bound to the views of the party, rather than the positions they hold and the responsibilities they have, not only to the American people, but are bound to by the American Constitution. Brilliant. If that does not show the grave danger to separation of power and checks and balances, nothing ever will.
A last warning on the state of nature: It's sort of like middle school, but they can kill you. Then where does that put an non-law-abiding national democracy? I dont remember stealing boyfriends and calling horrible names in Elementary school, and what could possibly be worse than junior high?!
Written by a member of Mr. Keopping's 7th period AP Government class at Lake Oswego High School

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, November 21, 2006 -- 4:00 PM

I would like to suggest an archetype for our const

I would like to suggest an archetype for our constitution's separation of powers that comes from ancient Greek philosophy.
The Stoics divided philosophy into three areas: logic, physics, and ethics. Recall that for the Greeks, and especially for the Stoics, philosophy was considered to be a wisdom-practice, or what the historian Pierre Hadot calls a "spiritual practice." This meant that ideally philosophy was something to which one committed one's life, living the pursuit of wisdom -- sophia -- which one embodied in one's very being. So philosophy was a first-person endeavor, in which one applied oneself to living in a certain way, guided by one's love of wisdom. "To live in accordance with nature," as the Stoics put it.
From this first-person perspective, the three divisions of philosophy stand out as having special significance. The psyche or soul itself has a three-fold function. It functions as a faculty of knowledge, which correlates with logic and epistemology. It also functions as a faculty of efficient causation, which correlates with ethics. Finally, it functions as a faculty of final causation, because our action is purposive, and this correlates with physics and the study of nature. In brief, the idea was that the study of logic improved one's faculty of knowledge, the study of physics improved one's faculty of final cause, and the study of ethics improved one's faculty of efficient cause.
Now, our constitution's separation of powers, I suggest, correlates with this Stoic division of philosophy and with the three faculties of the psyche. The judiciary correlates with the psyche's faculty of knowledge and the study of logic. The legislative correlates with the psyche's faculty of final causation and the study of physics. The executive correlates with the psyche's faculty of efficient causation and the study of ethics.
If my suggestion is correct, then it directly follows that any conception of the executive as the faculty of final causation is simply false. This function falls to the legislative, NOT the executive. The legislative carries out this function of final causation by passing law. The executive carries out the function of efficient causation by putting the law into effect.
How does my suggestion relate to the problems of a charismatic president? For one thing, it provides us with a distinction between the charismatic president who carries out his/her proper function (i.e., efficient causation), and the charismatic president who fails to carry out his/her proper function, but instead attempts to carry out the function of a different branch of government. Charisma in itself is not a bad thing, so long as it is charisma within the bounds of a branch's domain. But when the charisma extends to usurping the functions of the other branches of government, we've got a problem.
Right now, our president appears to be usurping the functions of both the judiciary and the legislative. His refusal to seek judiciary permission for warrantless searches and surveillance, and his substitution of courts controlled by the judiciary by courts controlled by the executive (e.g. military courts) represent, I believe, serious usurpation of the function of the judiciary, which is to evaluate knowledge claims and judge whether or not they meet standards of evidence. And, his outright refusal to obey the law passed by Congress, but instead to claim that his alleged "war powers" allow him to cherry-pick which laws he obeys, represents a serious usurpation of the function of the legislative branch, which is to evaluate possible goals for government action and choose which to pursue.
What lies at the end of this potential slippery slope of executive usurpation of function? The consolidation of all three functions of government into one single omnipotent branch. And this seems to me to be as good a definition as any of tyranny.
I would flesh this argument out further, but I don't have the time or resources right now. So I'm just putting it out there for readers' interest.
Cheers,
-paul

Guest's picture

Guest

Saturday, August 16, 2008 -- 5:00 PM

The link to KALW radio didn't work (for me at leas

The link to KALW radio didn't work (for me at least). Luckily, Googling "KALW radio" worked just fine. Glad to see your show is still on the air.

Guest's picture

Guest

Saturday, August 16, 2008 -- 5:00 PM

Ken's analysis of the intent of the constitution's

Ken's analysis of the intent of the constitution's framers derives from tyranny-prevention by checking executive power against legislative, and vice versa. In this it is seriously flawed, because, as he points out, the judiciary is left out, and the possible subject of potential tyranny is highly partial. It's well known, for example, that a main cause of the Revolutionary War was the level of prohibition by the Crown of colonial expropriation of native territory. In the final draft of the constitution, native inhabitants of expropriated land had to be included by the term "all others", in the provision in article 1 which insured landed control of the political process by afforded 3/5th's human-status to enslaved individuals for electoral purposes. So the goal of the framers is very far from tyranny prevention. Rather, as evidenced by subsequent events, the goal was, and in many respects continues to be, tyranny selectiveness.

Guest's picture

Guest

Friday, August 29, 2008 -- 5:00 PM

Monotheism developed almost in contradistinction f

Monotheism developed almost in contradistinction from the more usual polytheistic deities of ancient times. Perhaps it's the ulitmate political incorrectness to suggest that monarchies and then the U. S. presidency are corollaries of Monotheism. The U.S. presidencey is lately more and more defined in religious terms to such extent that in the most recent turn of political events, religious "values" have been made essentially the only qualification for presidency in what amounts to a mockery of any other qualifications.

Guest's picture

Guest

Friday, October 17, 2008 -- 5:00 PM

I can see why. She is very smart, very articulate,

I can see why. She is very smart, very articulate, and has really deep knowledge of constitutional law. It was a pleasure having her as our guest.

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, November 16, 2008 -- 4:00 PM

I think the key element here is that our Constitut

I think the key element here is that our Constitution is Newtonian in theory and Darwinian in practice. From the start, ours was meant to be something of a gravity-defying system of three independent spheres keeping each other up in the air. Much like the laws of physics, each Article carries a rather absolute view of their respective roles and given to a frustratingly inert movement of (radical) action. This is good for a democracy, but a threat to individual liberty as there are no explicit safeguards.
Enter Darwin and the Bill of Rights, and in particular the 14th Amendment to the Constitution. Through its prism we actually live and see our great text. Because the 14th Amendment makes it clear that all individuals born in the US shall not be deprived "of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws," it preserves individual rights, and thus the civil rights of minorities. (Majority Rule and Minority Rights)
This makes for a Constitution that ultimately evolves over time as with our guaranteed protections come an expectation of prompt enforcement of civil rights (re: Brown v. Board of Education; Hearts of Atlanta Motel v. Katzenbach; Loving v. Virginia, etc. el). It stands to reason, I think, that our country went from Jim Crow to Barack Obama because of the evolutionary pattern from a Constitution ignoring civil liberties and rights to sweepingly enforcing them in a period of 1 century. Most nations can only dream of such transformation; ours--well, there is a reason we are the United States of America.
In the case of the 1950's, it was the Supreme Court that first recognized civil rights, but ultimately, the Executive and then the Legislature, took decisive up the cause from there, and the rest, as they say, is history. When in concert, the branches are a check, but they can also be a weather vain on where the country is on any given issue, sort of like a scout. I am not so Congress or a president ever likes to be ahead of any issue without political cover.
XXX
As to the role of the charismatic leader, I would strongly challenge the point, Dr. Taylor. George Washington was America's first action hero and the quintessential charismatic leader. He was, after all, offered the opportunity to be dictator-for-life, but squashed that idea in its tracks.
If you look at the Constitution, you will find that the president has only the power to nominate and the power to veto. Yes, he can negotiate treaties, but here, as with his nominations, he needs the approval of the US Senate. But what he has above all else is his bully pulpit, and as history has shown, a President can achieve quite a bit with such power (FDR, TR, JFK, Reagan, Clinton, and even [awkwardly] G.W. Bush).
Washington got what he wanted through his force of personality, and ever since, each president has set themselves in that tradition, most notably in the 19th Century, Andrew Jackson and Abraham Lincoln, and the 20th, TR, Wilson, FDR, JFK, LBJ, Reagan, and Clinton.
This century, I predict President Obama to follow suit. If his race speech is any hint, I think we're in for quite an impressive catalog of great words matched with an even stronger impact.
So, as with so much of the Congress, the Courts, the presidency has evolved into a far more meatier and stronger institution than perhaps (in part) the Framers had in mind, but to assume they did not have this in mind, is totally bogus. Americans then as now, want strength. They want a leader who is bold when necessary and cautious when possible. They want a monarch without the bloodlines, a dictator with grueling oversight, and a statesman reigned in by our rule of law.
Oddly, that sounds more like Thomas Hobbes than John Locke!
NS

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, November 16, 2008 -- 4:00 PM

Oh, and I almost forgot! If you think Congress has

Oh, and I almost forgot! If you think Congress has lacked courage to protect their prerogatives, you need only look to history. As recently as 3 years ago, President Bush's policy on social security collapsed despite his major reelection victory, and the expansion of the House and Senate. FDR overreached with the Court packing plan, and with it, his domestic agenda all but ceased. He would never again get any major New Deal programs through, or be as powerful until World War II. Congress--much like the Courts--are slow to act by its institutional nature, it is not meant to react to every presidential move, but to reign in the excesses of executive power. The same is true of any president today or yesterday--and tomorrow!
The office is not charismatic--objects cannot bring charisma, but the leader's persona. Few have had much impact that did not have charismatic integrity. Sorry, Dr. Taylor, but you're misguided to believe otherwise. The office was meant to create a mystique on which to govern. For some, it has worked but for most, it has failed.
I could go on, but I've proven my poli sci skills long enough. The show is great. Keep up the GREAT work!
NS

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, November 23, 2008 -- 4:00 PM

It seems to me that the founders ? and even Mont

It seems to me that the founders ? and even Montesquieu, the inventor of the separation of powers ? lacked prescience not only on the charismatic nature of presidency and the wheight of partisan loyalty, but also of a third "big fact": the development of the "fifth power", that is television (after Orwell's fourth power: the press). Television coverage of Irak war has been the main way to convince people of the rightness of this war. Television, more than other media, may push in a direction or another depending on what people watch. The fifth power is overwhelming in driving people's attention and interest. In countries where media are directly owned by a politician the separation of powers itself seems to be in danger: in Italy the Prime Minister Silvio Berlusconi owns three main private channels and has a big influence on the other three public channels; in Thainland the Prime Minister Thaksin Shinawatra owned the main company of telecommunication, media and e-business, before being deposed in military coup in 2006. Probably internet connection had a big role in last US elections, and it may partly counter-balance the "big media" influence. But speaking of separation of powers should involve attention of the agenda given by the main television channels and to the abundance of "charismatic" figures which prompt everywhere as political leaders pushed from visual media (and not only the charismatic nature of the presidency).

Guest's picture

Guest

Thursday, July 9, 2009 -- 5:00 PM

Limited Government In Relation to Some Fields of P

Limited Government In Relation to Some Fields of Power Prohibited to the Federal Government
The Constitution's enumeration of powers granted to the Federal government is summed up by Madison in The Federalist number 45, as we have seen, as being: ". . . few and defined . . . will be exercised principally on external objects, as war, peace, negociation, and foreign commerce . . ." It is of interest to note briefly some principal examples of fields of power which are prohibited to the Federal government by the Constitution, as amended to the present writing.
In The Federalist number 17, Hamilton decried the idea that the new Federal government--to be created under the Constitution, then in process of ratification--would not respect the strict limits on its powers as prescribed in this fundamental law but would usurp the reserved powers of the States; as was being asserted by those who were extremely fearful of any central government with substantial powers and were arguing in favor of stricter and clearer limits on Federal power. Chief among these were Patrick Henry, Richard Henry Lee and Samuel Adams. Hamilton here mentioned commerce, finance, negotiation, and war as being the principal fields of power properly delegated to the Federal government but he expressly made it clear that agriculture is excluded. He classified agriculture as a field belonging to the reserved powers of the States--as one which could never properly be under the control of the central government:
"The administration of private justice between the citizens of the same state, the supervision of agriculture and of other concerns of a similar nature, all those things in short which are proper to be provided for by local legislation, can never be desireable cares of a general jurisdiction."
By "general jurisdiction" he meant the Federal government. The field of agriculture was no doubt chosen by Hamilton for specific mention here because it was common knowledge--not only among those who had framed the Constitution but among all other leaders as well as the people at large---that nothing would have been considered more unarguably and absurdly false than any claim that the activities of people engaged in agriculture would be subject to Federal regulation or control, directly or indirectly, under the Constitution's wording as understood by The Framers and Adopters and everyone else.
Several other illustrations of prohibited power were provided by President Jefferson in his Second Inaugural Address. He discussed the constructive uses of any possible surplus revenues of the Federal government and mentioned some which he stated are outside of the scope of power of this government under the Constitution, expressly noting that an amendment of the fundamental law would be necessary before such use could be made of any surplus of tax monies:
". . . by a just repartition among the states, and a corresponding amendment of the constitution, be applied, in time of peace, to rivers, canals, roads, arts, manufactures, education, and other great objects within each state." (Emphasis added, except "in time of peace" emphasized in the original.)
In other words, Federal spending for these specified purposes was not authorized by the Constitution--these fields of activity being excluded from the scope of the Federal government's power under the Constitution; so an amendment would be necessary in order to give any such spending the necessary sanction through the properly expressed consent of the people. In his sixth annual Message to the Congress in 1806, Jefferson again discussed possible surplus revenues and their use in such fields requiring a constitutional amendment:
". . . application to the great purposes of the public education, roads, rivers, canals, and such other objects of public improvement as it may be thought proper to add to the constitutional enumeration of federal powers . . . I suppose an amendment to the constitution, by consent of the States, necessary, because the objects now recommended are not among those enumerated in the constitution, and to which it permits the public moneys to be applied." (Emphasis added.)
It is particularly interesting to note that Jefferson here soundly distinguished between using Federal monies to aid education (mentioning particularly a national institution of scientific learning )--which he stated is unauthorized, unless and until an amendment to the Constitution would be adopted authorizing it; and, on the other hand, aiding education by making land-grants from the colossal holdings of virgin and unsettled land already owned by the Federal government (by occupation, purchase or conquest from the Indians and foreign governments), which he stated the Congress "now have it in their power" so to use. Such aid to education by Federal land-grants was already customary; it had been commenced under the Confederation and was generally considered to be within the powers of the Federal government under the Constitution--but not so as to tax-monies in the Federal treasury.
Special emphasis is needed with regard to the basis of this distinction between such Federal land-grants and money-grants, as to constitutionality: the Federal government has the power to dispose of land and other property it owns (Art. IV, Sec. 3) and, furthermore, single-transaction land-grants could not possibly accomplish the unconstitutional objective of permitting it to obtain, in effect, any control over the recipients. On the other hand, the Constitution did not specify aid to education as one of the purposes for which the Federal government (specifically the Congress) might tax and spend; and furthermore periodic, or regular, grants of money could not but have the practical effect of giving this government--perhaps indirectly, gradually and subtly but nevertheless inescapably--substantially controlling influence over the recipient institutions, or persons. This is due partly to the reason cited by Hamilton in The Federalist number 79: "In the general course of human nature, a power over a man's subsistence amounts to a power over his will." (Emphasis Hamilton's.) In other words, "he who pays the piper calls the tune." Such control can even be effectively manifested negatively, by creating inhibitions on the part of the recipient of the subsidy or grant of funds, rather than through control affirmatively and outrightly. For example, those who would hope for a Federal grant in the future--such as a scholar, or a college--would be strongly inclined to refrain from criticism of this government regarding things which would otherwise be freely and vigorously condemned as unsound.
This is why Hamilton, as Secretary of the Treasury, carefully restricted his contention in 1791 so as to exclude Federal control, when he first argued in favor of the idea that the Taxing Clause gives the Federal government a separate and substantive power for the "application of money," within the limits of what would serve the general welfare. He also stated, in another document, that it would not ". . . imply a power to do whatever else should appear to Congress conducive to the general welfare" and continued:
"A power to appropriate money with this latitude, which is granted, too, in express terms, would not carry a power to do any other thing not authorized in the Constitution, either expressly or by fair implication." (1791 "Opinion as to the Constitutionality of the Bank of the United States"; and 1791 Report on "Manufactures.")
The Taxing Clause, using the words "general Welfare," (Art. I, Sec. 8) states: "The Congress shall have Power To lay and collect Taxes, Duties, Imposts and Excises, to pay the Debts and provide for the common Defence and general Welfare of the United States . . ."
Hamilton always denied that this clause gives Congress a general legislative authority--to legislate regarding, and so as to achieve, whatever Congress might consider to be for the common good. He never varied from his assertion in The Federalist number 83, regarding the plan of the Framing Convention expressed in the Constitution, with regard to such authority, as follows:
"The plan of the convention declares that the power of congress or in other words of the national legislature, shall extend to certain enumerated cases. This specification of particulars evidently excludes all pretension to a general legislative authority; because an affirmative grant of special powers would be absurd as well as useless, if a general authority was intended." (Emphasis per original.)
Hamilton never contended for--indeed, he evidently would have opposed strenuously--use of the Federal power to tax and spend so as in effect to give the Federal government indirectly any control over anything, or anybody, which is not directly and openly authorized by the Constitution and its amendments through enumeration of the powers granted to it by the people. He would undoubtedly have agreed with the distinction which Jefferson drew--in the above-mentioned addresses made after Hamilton's death--with regard to Federal aid to Education: that land-grants in aid of education are constitutional, partly because they could not possibly produce any degree of control over the recipient institutions due to such grants being a single-transaction measure as to each of the recipient institutions.
The opposite would be true as to Federal grants of monies periodically, because they could not possibly avoid producing the effect of substantial control over the recipient--however gradual, or subtle, or indirect, or negative (by creating inhibitions) and regardless of how arranged so as to conceal the element of control. In the 1936 Butler case, the Supreme Court truly stated (pages 70-71 of opinion): "The power to confer or withhold unlimited benefits is the power to coerce or destroy;" and it restated (pages 73-74) and applied the cardinal, constitutional principle that what the Constitution does not specifically empower the Federal government to do directly, so as to be able to exercise control, ". . . it may not indirectly accomplish those ends by taxing and spending to purchase compliance." In other words, a power granted by the Constitution may not be misused by this government so as in effect to enable it indirectly to exercise a power which has not been so granted and therefore has been prohibited to it. While in the related Wickard case (1942) the Court asserted [correctly, but only if it be true that the particular subsidy is authorized by the Constitution] that: "It is hardly lack of due process for the Government to regulate that which it subsidizes." (Page 131 of opinion; here "regulate" means control.) Judged by his writings, including his 1791 assertions noted above, Hamilton would have agreed and would have disapproved, as unconstitutional, any and all subsidy-and-control schemes of the Federal government except such as might be directly and clearly authorized by the people, by a constitutional amendment, empowering this government so to control openly and directly the persons, or institutions, subsidized. Madison and all of the other Framers and Adopters of the Constitution also would have agreed--Jefferson, too.
The fields of power denied to the Federal government by the Constitution, according to both Hamilton and Jefferson--agriculture, education and so on, as noted above---could be multiplied by citing other writings by them and other Founders; but this is unnecessary for present purposes and would not take into account any additions to Federal power authorized by subsequent amendments. It is desirable, therefore, to quote here a modern writing which correctly reflects the views of The Framers and Adopters as to the initial instrument's exclusion of fields of power from Federal control and, in addition, takes into account all amendments to the present period.
A 1930 writing which fills this need is available; and, in addition, it is an excellent and concise discussion of the traditional American philosophy and system of government regarding especially the nature and importance of decentralization of power ("States Rights") as a mainstay of the security of the people's liberties. The Constitution has not been amended since 1930 to increase Federal power, so this writing in effect speaks as of today with regard to the extent of Federal powers; indeed, they have since been decreased by repeal of the 18th ("Prohibition") Amendment by adoption in 1933 of the 21st Amendment. This 1930 writing is cited for the further reason that it is couched in simple terms and presents only ideas which were then common knowledge and accepted truths among the American people--even among Youth with a normal high-school education for that period--as well as among the people through all generations from 1787 to 1930. The writing is cited not because it expressed anything new, or any original thinking of its author but, on the contrary, because it did not do so. Its special usefulness and value stem from the fact that it merely re-stated the traditional view as always understood and supported up to 1930 by all competent scholars and authorities--including the three Branches of the Federal government, especially the Supreme Court--as well as by leaders and the American people in general. This widespread understanding was such in 1930 that, if the valedictorian of a graduating class of a college, or even of a high school, had then made this address as the one usual on such an occasion, the audience would justly have applauded on the ground that there was nothing in it but long-accepted truths so well known that it merely evidenced the young orator's being soundly and reasonably well-informed regarding the elementary simplicities of the traditional American philosophy and system of constitutionally limited and decentralized power and its fundamental importance to the safety of the American people's God-given, unalienable rights.
This writing referred to is the March 2, 1930 "States Rights" address of Governor Franklin D. Roosevelt of New York--the full text of which, for the foregoing reasons, is set forth in the Appendix to this study-guide. This Address--made as an appeal to the American people for support of his plan to be elected President and presenting some of the basic principles which, he impliedly assured them, he would if elected faithfully support--was in criticism of any concentration of power in Washington in violation of the Constitution's limits on Federal power.
The entire address merits careful study for the reasons previously noted; but, at this point in the present discussion of fields of power prohibited to the Federal government by the Constitution as amended, the following short quotation will suffice:
"As a matter of fact and law, the governing rights of the States are all of those which have not been surrendered to the National Government by the Constitution or its amendments. Wisely or unwisely, people know that under the Eighteenth Amendment Congress has been given the right to legislate on this particular subject, but this is not the case in the matter of a great number of other vital problems of government, such as the conduct of public utilities, of banks, of insurance, of business, of agriculture, of education, of social wel[are and of a dozen other important features. In these, Washington must not be encouraged to interfere." (Emphasis added.)
To repeat, the Constitution has never been amended since 1930 so as to increase the Federal government's power. Since then, no amendment has granted it any power to control any of the prohibited fields of power specified by Hamilton, Jefferson and Roosevelt as mentioned above. It is of unusual interest to note that agriculture---expressly listed by Hamilton in 1787 and by Roosevelt as of 1930 as being among the fields of power prohibited to the Federal government by the Constitution--was the subject of the above-mentioned Butler case (1936): There the Supreme Court confirmed the fact of such prohibition, in deciding that the Federal law under consideration--seeking to subsidize and control agriculture--violated the Constitution's limits on Federal power and therefore was null and void, judged by this instrument's original meaning which the Court correctly ruled is controlling unless and until the people change these limits by due amendment of this basic law.
It is a fundamental principle of the American philosophy that the people themselves, as well as their public servants who are sworn to support the Constitution faithfully, must respect the existing limits on the Federal government's power under the Constitution, as amended; which can be changed by the people only by its amendment. Referring to the amending process as a "solemn and authoritative act," Hamilton stated the principle (previously noted) in The Federalist number 78 as follows: "Until the people have by some solemn and authoritative act annulled or changed the established form, it is binding upon themselves collectively, as well as individually; and no presumption, or even knowledge of their sentiments, can warrant their representatives in a departure from it, prior to such an act." (Here "sentiments" refers to public opinion in favor of some measure not authorized by the Constitution.) The reason why this principle is so basically important was stressed in Washington's Farewell Address as follows:
"If in the opinion of the People, the distribution or modification of the Constitutional powers be in any particular wrong, let it be corrected by an amendment in the way which the Constitution designates. But let there be no change by usurpation; for though this, in one instance, may be the instrument of good, it is the customary weapon by which free governments are destroyed. The precedent must always greatly overbalance in permanent evil any partial or transient benefit which the use can at any time yield."
This highlights the tremendous importance of the American people's being always soundly informed with respect to the limits on the Federal government's power under the Constitution; as amended, in order to be able to perform adequately the duties inherent in Individual Liberty-Responsibility and thus make possible the enduring safety of their God-given, unalienable rights and Posterity's just heritage of Individual Liberty and its supporting system.
"Vindiciamus"