Week of: 
May 6, 2007
What is it: 

Philosophers call a person autonomous if she is responsible not just for what she does but also for the priciples and rules that guide her. But does this really make sense? Aren't we all just products of culture, education and genes? Join John and Ken as they investigate the nature of autonomy with John Christman from Penn State University.

Listening Notes: 

Autonomy: illusion or reality?  Before turning to guest John Christman, John and Ken decide that autonomy is a sort of self-government wherein an individual lives by their own rules and lives a free life.  Christman agrees with John and Ken that autonomy is best understood as self-government, but he is careful to distinguish autonomy from freedom—freedom refers to action whereas autonomy refers to the internal conditions that move someone to act.  Christman also disagrees that autonomy means making up your own rules, if that’s true its unclear why autonomy is a value and whether autonomy is even possible.  Instead, Christman asserts that autonomy is more like self-management than self-creation—and self-management is the ability to effectively pursue our desires as opposed to blindly following them. 

John agrees with Christman’s definition and decides to flesh it out with an example.  Let’s say a man decides to become a vegetarian.  This autonomous decision isn’t made any less autonomous because someone else created the idea of vegetarianism and told him adopted the practice.  Christman likes this example, it illustrates his point that autonomy is a state of thinking over one’s values and endorsing them.  What makes a vegetarian autonomous would not be creating the idea of vegetarianism but reflecting on the idea of vegetarianism and deciding to become one.  Ken objects, he says this definition sounds more like thoughtfulness than autonomy.  Christman acknowledges his definition is philosophically problematic – if autonomy is examining one’s desires then we may run into an infinite regress of desires.  The first desire is not to eat meat, and the second desire is not to harm animals,  and the third desire is to do as little harm in ones life as possible, and so forth ad infinitum.

Ken challenges Christman again, asking Christman about an autonomous Satan.  Should a purely evil person’s autonomy be respected?  Christman identifies two approaches to this problem.  The first, Kantian approach is to say that  the capacity to impose upon ourselves moral principles is the seat of all moral responsibility and obligation.  So if someone is satanic, or they embrace evil principles it is unclear what sort of respect we owe them.  The second approach, which Christman calls the observer point of view  demands that when we interact with other people we owe them some respect, respect their autonomy.  If someone who knows the difference between good and bad chooses to do bad we may punish them but in the end we still owe them some respect, we still grant them some autonomy. 

In the final segment of the episode, John, Ken and Christman consider the relationship between autonomy and democracy.  John thinks we need autonomous thinkers to make democratic decisions.  But then after that we reach consensus we want everyone to follow these rules, regardless of their desires.  Ken is still uninspired by this definition of autonomy.  What John and Christman call autonomy sounds more like reflection and the simple act of weighing costs and benefits before making a decision.  Christman concludes that the autonomous component  of the democratic process is being able to weigh these costs and benefits in the first place.  The autonomous self is produced by this ability to give reasons for our actions and interact with other people.

  • Polly Stryker the Roving Philosophical Reporter (seek to 4:40)  Polly considers one person’s autonomous decision to leave a career in physics and become a philosopher.
  • Ian Shoals the Sixty-Second Philosopher (seek to 50:01) Ian addresses complaints that his so-called sixty-second philosophies are almost always longer than sixty-seconds. 

John Christman, Professor of Philosophy, Political Science, and Women's Studies, Pennsylvania State University

Related Resources: 

Get Philosophy Talk


Sunday at 10am, PST, KALW, 91.7 FM, Local Public Radio, San Francisco


Individual Downloads  via CdBaby or Itunes.  Multipacks and The Complete Philosophy Talk via Iamplify

John Perry and Ken Taylor

Continue the Conversation

Sidebar Menu

Upcoming Shows

  • November 29 : Your Lying Eyes - Perception, Memory, and Justice
    The criminal justice system often relies on the testimony of eyewitnesses to get convictions. Yet more and more, psychological science demonstrates...
  • December 6 : Self and Self-Presentation
    We craft personal brands or images to accompany or represent ourselves in various situations. These personas are malleable – how we portray ourselves...
  • December 13 : Taoism: Following the Way
    Taoism (sometimes Daoism) is one of the great philosophical traditions of China. Lao-Tzu, commonly regarded as its founder, said that “Those who know...
  • December 20 : Good, Evil, and the Divine Plan
    A theodicy is an explanation by a philosopher or theologian about why a world created by a kind and all-powerful God contains so much suffering. It...
  • December 27 : Truth and Other Fictions
    Most of us think we know the truth when we see it. But what exactly is truth, anyway? Philosophers have offered a blizzard of different answers,...

Support Philosophy Talk


Philosophy Talk relies on the support of listeners like you to stay on the air and online. Any contribution, large or small, helps us produce intelligent, reflective radio that questions everything, including our most deeply-held beliefs about science, morality, culture, and the human condition. Make your tax-deductible contribution now through Stanford University's secure online donation page. Thank you for your support, and thank you for thinking!